Back to CQ
Homepage
Back to Archives' Table of Contents
Qualia and Computers
by Teed Rockwell
In my last post, I described two sets of
currently respectable concepts that seemed to presuppose the existence of sense
data: qualia theory and computer theory. Since then, I've had some correspondence
with David Chalmers between posts which seems to indicate that in his case, at
least, the connection between sense data and qualia may take some work to unravel.
(and remember folks, you read it here first!). Computer theory, on the other hand,
now appears to me to be actually incompatible with sense datum theory. The
criticisms of my original claim to the contrary have shown me that there is another
concept which I was conflating with sense data: the psychologist's concept of
sensation. This latter concept is far more resilient, but may be vulnerable to more
subtle critiques found in the works of psychologists J.J. and E.J. Gibson. Those
who are more interested in Psychology than Philosophy might want to skip ahead to
the next section. I need a lot of input from psychologists on what Sue Pockett
calls "this restricted trade sense" of sensation, and how it relates to the more
cognitive concept of perception. But I also think that having Chalmers clarify his
position on the relationship between sense data and qualia is helpful for those of
us who are interested in understanding his
ideas.
CHALMERS ON SENSE DATA AND QUALIA
Chalmers first response to the last CQ Post was the
following:
It's one thing to believe in qualia (phenomenal properties, characterizing what
it's like to be in a given mental state). it's a quite different thing to believe
in sense data (considered as the foundation of all perceptual knowledge, the things
we observe directly in indirectly observing the world). There are fairly strong
reasons based in epistemology and the philosophy of perception for rejecting the
latter, but none of these reasons provide grounds for rejecting the
former.
I suppose that sense data, if they existed, would be qualia, but it's not the
case that qualia must be sense data, at least in the objectionable sense. . . (e.g.
re kane's point, while i believe in qualia, i certainly don't believe that
perception is the "passive reception of data".)
(***)
I gathered from this that Chalmers might think that many of the characteristics
shared by sense data and qualia ought to be removed from the latter concept. So I
sent him this post (the list below I got from Owen Flanagan's "Consciousness
Reconsidered"):
qualia and sense data are both usually considered to
be:
1)intrinsic 2)atomic 3) Unanalyzable 4)non-relational 5)ineffable 6)essentially
private 7)immediately corrigible and
apprehensible.
I think that most concepts of sense data would include all of these. Are there
any you would not include in your concept of qualia? And if Chalmersian qualia lack
any of these characteristics, what do they have instead, in each
case?(***)
To which Chalmers replied:
i think qualia are certainly intrinsic and nonrelational. they are at least
partly effable (e.g. i can describe their structure), though they may be partly
ineffable. i don't know whether they are atomic or unanalyzable -- these notions
would have to be spelled out better -- but i am tempted to say "not necessarily". i
think they are essentially private in a sense, and i think they are immediately
apprehensible.
obviously sense data and qualia have many characteristics in common. given that
a sense datum, if it exists, will be a quale. . .. but the reverse doesn't hold:
sense data are generally taken to have further properties, e.g. they are the
foundation of all perceptual knowledge and they are what we observe directly when
we observe the external world indirectly, and these are the aspects of the doctrine
of sense data that are most widely attacked. there's no reason why a supporter of
qualia needs to say that qualia have these properties.
(***)
To which I replied:
1)Owen Flanagan said that even though he agreed with Dennett that Qualia don't
have these characteristics, that doesn't prove that there are no such things as
Qualia. It seems, however, that you really do believe in just the sort of Qualia
that Dennett wants to "Quine."
2)Lets look at the properties that you say qualia need not have but which sense
data do have. . . It seems to me that once we. . . shift the discussion to
epistemology, the properties you attribute to qualia make them hard to distinguish
from sense data. If they are immediately apprehensible, this would mean that our
knowledge of them would be directly observed which would make them a foundation for
our other knowledge, which is only indirectly observed. . . It also seems that once
you have bought into the idea that qualia are intrinsic and non-relational, you
also have to accept that they are immediately apprehensible. If their properties
are completely intrinsic, they cannot be apprended by relating them to other
things, which leaves unmediated apprehension as the only way of being aware of
them.
Maybe this is not the only explanation for why qualia have the characteristics
you give them, but it seems the most obvious one, and it also seems pretty closely
tied up with the concept of sense data. My only real point is that separating
qualia from sense data is a job that still needs to be done by any sense-dataphobic
qualiaphile, which is why sense datum theory is not as dead a horse as is generally
believed. Dead horses, despite their numerous other failings, do not require us to
clean up after them.(***)
Chalmers replied with:
Sure, I tend to believe in the qualia Dennett wants to quine. I don't
necessarily buy all four properties straight up (it depends on how you analyze
them), but i have some sympathy for privacy, immediate apprehensibility, and
intrinsicness; ineffability is tricky. I don't think Dennett has good arguments
against the first three (in the relevant
sense).
I don't think immediate apprehensibility implies epistemic foundationalism
about external knowledge. The fact that we immediately apprehend qualia doesn't
imply that our knowlege of the rest of the world is by virtue of our knowledge of
qualia. for example, the qualia freak might simply take the nonfoundationalist's
picture about external knowledge and say that picture works for the external, so
qualia don't play an essential role there. and there are other subtler stories one
can tell, involving qualia but not founding all knowledge of knowledge of qualia.
(a qualia freak might even hold that knowledge of the external world comes before
knowledge of qualia, even if the latter is more certain than the
former.)(***)
My last post to Chalmers was:
Lets take a look at some of these logical possiblities, and see whether there
are any you would want to actually accept. Do you really want to say that we have a
direct awareness of the inhabitants of our inner space, but that we don't use this
direct awareness in any way to help us learn about the outside world? This would
strongly imply that qualia have no significant connection to the outside world that
we could make use of. . . And yet surely this is false; If there such things as
qualia, then most of the time when we sense red-apple shaped qualia, it is because
there is an apple in front of us. So if qualia are directly grasped, they are
clearly telling us a great deal about the world most of the time. How could we have
another source of knowledge that was more reliable than this? It seems the only way
we can have a nonfoundationalist view of knowledge is to assume that qualia are not
directly grasped in this way. Otherwise our knowledge of qualia would beat out any
other source of knowledge we had.
I think most of the hard problems of consciousness that you raise would still
be worthy of consideration if we cast them as bridging the gap between the third
person and the first person perspective. I don't think we need to say that the
first person perspective reveals a whole menagerie of entities that are distinct
from those encountered from the third person perspective. Don't you find it
ontologically offensive to posit the existance of both red apples and red apple
shaped qualia, grey elephants and grey elephant shaped qualia, and so on ad
infinitum?. . .I don't think that we need to posit a separate category for mental
things that is more ontologically distinct than say the category of social things.
We still have a big problem to deal with when we consider the fact that my
brain/etc. states seem very different to me than they do to you. But we don't have
to posit the existance of directly apprehended qualia to acknowledge that this is a
problem.(***)
I don't know whether Chalmers will acknowledge this, but it seems to me that he
still has some work to do before he can claim that his qualia are completely
distinct from sense data. However, I think that this separation can be
accomplished, and that both Flanagan's book and the last paragraph of mine above
give some indication of how it could be done. (Michael Tye's article in the On-line
"Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy" also mentions the close relationship between
sense data and qualia, and his suggestion for separating the two is quite similar
to Flanagan's.)
SENSE DATA, SENSATIONS, AND COMPUTERS.
In the previous CQ post, I claimed that any attempt to apply computer theory to
understanding human cognition would presuppose the existence of sense data. Jim
Garson very effectively disposed of this claim with the following
critique:
. . .it is far from clear that the inputs {in classical computer theory} could
even possibly be encountered AS sensations. For that, one would need to encounter
inputs related to others in the right kinds of ways and this would involve finding
the data within a cognitive level theoretical structure of some kind.... raw
inputs by this very theory cannot count as the sensations, since their
individuation AS sensations requires a framework of interrelations provided by the
functionalist theory that undergirds the identification of mental
states.
I am reminded of a parallel moral to be drawn about computers. Imagine we have
a simple caclulator set up to do addition and subtraction. The raw input might be
arrays of 0s and 1s (or more carefully, switch settings). These have no status as
NUMERICAL inputs until we encounter their computational roles defined by the
machine. Computer states do not take on their intentional properties in a vacuum.
This is the sense that inputs mathematically construed ( i.e. intentionally
construed) are never "raw". This is an important Kantian theme in classical
computationalism that seems to me to challenge features of "whole hog" sense data
theory. Further evidence that the horse is long dead.
(***)
Andy Clark adds the following:
At times, I felt you just might be failing to distinguish the idea of sense
data from the idea of MERE INPUT. The point about sense data was that they were
meant to be both RAW and yet somehow REALLY CONTENTFUL: a combination that looks
ultimately incoherent. All that information theory really needs is the idea of an
input to the system, and a set of actions to select from on the basis of that
input. (***)
These comments, in conjunction with some comments made by Sue Pockett and
others, made me realise that I had been conflating SENSE DATA with SENSATIONS:two
closely related (but crucially different) concepts, one from philosophy and the
other from psychology.
A sense datum is a single moment in sensory experience which is supposedly
directly given to the perceiver, from which he indirectly infers the existence of
objects. It is sense datum theory that prompted one analytic philosopher (I think
it was C.D. Broad) to claim that we directly perceive an eliptical penny, and from
this infer the existence of a round, three dimensional one. The best way to
understand a sense datum is to conceive of it as a single frame of film in the
moving picture which is our sensory experience. This is why I think that sense
datum theory inspired Edison to invent the moving picture, which is a pretty
impressive accomplishment for a false theory. (It would be interesting to research
Edison's letters or diaries to see whether he consciously acknowledged this.)
Ullin (U.T.) Place also contributed another
effective criticism of the philosopher's sense
datum:
After filling a particularly deep cavity in one of my teeth recently, my
dentist asked me to check any pain I might subsequently have to see whether it was
caused equally by hot and cold stimuli (good) or only by hot (bad, particulary if
throbbing). This, however, is a rather sophisticated form of observation which we
learn only AFTER we have already learned to observe what is going on in the world
around us. When I say I rejected the doctrine of sense-data more than fifty years
ago, what I rejected was the idea that in observing what is going on around us, we
begin by observing our sensory experience, formulate those observations in the form
of a sentence in a private sense datum language and then use those private
observation sentences as evidence for the existence and nature of what we NEVER
observe, namely the objects and situations in the world around us.
(***)
(Note: Place also makes this same point in his classic paper "Is consciousness
a brain process?", in which he calls this mistake "the phenomenological fallacy".
In his CQ post, he gave a detailed analysis of why sense data have to be more like
sentences, rather than pictures, in order to do the job that is required by the
classical theory. He may be right about this, but I think that most believers in
sense datum theory see them as more like pictures, even if they have no right to do
so. Also, as Place points out in the post, the fact that they can't be sentences
for other reasons is one of the weaknessess of sense datum theory. {note: Place's
complete post is in the Commentators
Respond--WTR.)
This kind of sense datum theory is, I now think, a completely dead horse, and
well it should be, for these and many other reasons. However, Psychologists have
apparently dealt with these objections by making a distinction between PERCEPTIONS
and SENSATIONS. I have yet to find a specific definition for these two terms and
would be grateful for any references. From what I can tell from reading between the
lines in various texts, however, perceptions are structured from sensations by
various kinds of processing. In retrospect, I should have realized that there is a
tremendous difference between a tabula rasa and an information processor, even
though both of them need input to have content. The input to a tabula rasa is
conceived of as a complete picture, but the input to an information processor is a
bit or unit which is shaped into a picture (or a sentence etc.) by computational
processes. The perceived picture is thus constructed out of bit-like sensations,
but it is the sensations that give us contact with the outside
world.
Once I became aware of this distinction, I realized that computer science is in
fact more Kantian than empiricist, despite my earlier claims that implied the
contrary. But Kant was in his own way a kind of empiricist, for he was a firm
disbeliever in what he called "intellectual intuition". He thought that we got all
of our information about our world from the sense organs, except for those a priori
forms that were hard-wired in. I'm tempted to say something here like "information
without computation is blind, computation without information is empty.", to
paraphrase Kant's famous statement about the relationship between concepts and
intuitions.
The following selections are from a post by Peter Lloyd, which I had described
in the last CQ post as "a post from a Computer person, (lost during the great data
disaster), which defended sense datum theory because it was essential to computer
science." Now that Lloyd has re-sent that post, it seems to me that what he was
really defending was sensations, not sense
data:
1. I can't see how a non-sensationalistic epistemology can ever get off the
ground. The mind is (amongst other things) an information-processing system that
uses information successfully in interacting with its environment. Therefore the
mind possesses information. But it is a fundamental characteristic of information
that it is *not* endlessly reducible. The analysis of information comes to an end
with raw data. Therefore the mind possesses basic units of information, which we
might call 'raw data' or 'sensations'. (***)
Lloyd then adds some qualifiers that blur the analogy with
computers.
2. Talking to pragmatists in the past, I've got the impression that they think
of sensations only as 'naive' sensations. For instance, if you think of your
visual field as consisting of pixels of visual sensation like a TV screen, then
that's what I'm calling a naive view of sensations. In fact, the sensations that
make up the visual field must be more complex and subtle than that. Nevertheless,
the visual field still consists of sensations. (I am thinking here of Hubel &
Wiesel's experiments, and my own experiences of migraine 'castellations', which
suggest larger visual elements as the raw units.)
(***)
(Anyone know anything about Hubel and Wiesel's experiments, and how they apply
to this problem?) {Note:I received these posts from Bickle and Pockett in response to this
question.--WTR}
some questions: If the fundamental sensationalistic "atoms" are more complex
than pixels, does this complexity come from the world or is it "cooked up" by our
perceptual-cognitive processes? And if the latter, what right do we have to call
them raw units? ( The pun has real significance, I think.) A little further down
in his post, Lloyd says that when we are "hearing phonemes belonging to a language
with which we are familiar, those phonemes *are* the raw conscious sensations." So
apparently even a history of learning to recognize patterns does not stop those
patterns from being "raw". The thing that makes them raw is apparently the fact
that "What the brain then delivers to the conscious mind are indivisible,
unanalysable units of raw sensation." What happens in the wings of the Cartesian
theater is apparently irrelevant; if we experience a sensation as unanalyzable, it
is unanalyzable. Lloyd also says that "sensations do not come *into* the mind from
outside. . . They are constructed internally in response to incoming stimuli." This
rules out Clark's view that sensations are themselves input, if they are only
responses to input.
So it looks from this description that sensations do not actually produce the
results they are posited to explain: They do not present us with any aspect
whatsoever of what is going on right now in unprocessed raw form, and they do not
get us in contact with the outside world. What Lloyd is describing is very like
Kant's view of a conscious being that creates a world in response to a
thing-in-itself, without ever being able to actually experience the
thing-in-itself. One significant difference between Lloyd's view and Kant's is
that the former permits us to *know* things about the world even though we can't
*experience* it. Our science, after all, enables us to make inferences about the
outside world, even though, according to this view, we never encounter the world
face to face. And it is also acknowledged that somehow the outside world affects
our phenomenal experience, and positing the existance of sensations seems to be a
way of trying to acknowledge this. But it is not all clear to me exactly what
sensations are, and how they differ from the other processes that consitute
perceptual experience. I seem to remember that Kant had a great deal to say about
this subject, and if anyone can cite or paraphrase him on this issue, I would be
grateful (Mark Steidle?) But because Kant said that the outside world was not only
inexperienceable but unknowable, I don't think that most modern scientific realists
would be willing to follow his arguments to their
conclusions.
None of this is a criticism of what Lloyd has written. In fact, I think he has
done a beautiful job of capturing the tensions and inconsistencies in the
perception-sensation distinction. Although Lloyd refers to himself humbly as " a
professional software developer and an amateur philosopher" I think he has given
this position about as good a defense as it can get (which is why I want to abandon that position and look for
something better.) And I think I can see something on the horizon in the works of
the pragmatists, in J.J. Gibson, and in the works of Andy Clark and Ruth Millikan.
This post is already longer than it should be, so I will only mention that J.J.
Gibson says on p.319 of "the Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems" that
"Sensations are not, as we have always taken for granted, the basis of perception."
His arguments for this position are scattered throughout his writings, and like
most scientists he is more interested in facts than in teasing out their
philosophical implications. The Millikan paper I mentioned at the end of the last
CQ post, and Andy Clark's book "Being There", seem to build on Gibson's scientific
work to some degree, so perhaps they will also end up agreeing with him on this
point. In the meantime, if anyone has either defenses or criticisms of Gibson's
position on sensations, I would love to hear them. From what I understand, Gibson
is a controversial figure in Psychology, and I want to be able to hear both sides
of the controversy. And when we start to talk about Gibson's concept of
affordances, I think we will probably start to discover connections to Pragmatism
and the Pragmatist concept of experience.
I also have a couple of other very nice long posts. John Bickle sent me a detailed
critique of Sergio Chaigneau's post, which I am forwarding to Sergio. John, Sergio,
and I may have a side conversation that is more neurologically oriented, so anyone
who wants to be in on that should let me know. Markate Daly also pointed out some significant
differences between the pragmatist concept of experience and the
knowing-how/knowing-that distinction, and proposed a very ingenious explanation
for some of the problems of the sensory given. Markate's post will probably be
important when we are considering Ruth Millikan's paper on
knowing-how/knowing-that, as will the second half of Clark's post. In the meantime,
keep those cards and letters coming in, Folks. As I said before, I read everything
I get several times, and things that haven't been posted yet may be posted later.
Thanks for joining me in the pursuit of truth, for want of a better
word.
Teed Rockwell