6/17/96
Dear Teed Rockwell,
I have read your paper `On what the mind is identical with'
with interest, though not, as you can imagine with
agreement. You state that, according to Smart and myself,
"every mental state or event is identical with some
material state or event." That is not and never has been
my view. My contention was and is that it is a reasonable
and, when fully spelled out, empirically testable
hypothesis that a particular aspect of the mental life of
the more highly developed of complex free-moving living
organisms (animals) which I refer to as `consciousness' is
a particular process or pattern of activity in the brains
of such creatures. Consciousness in this sense is
essentially an ongoing process. It is neither a mental
state, if by that is meant a dispositional state, nor an
event, if by that is meant an instantaneous event, such as
a decision or the occurrence of a thought.
Dispositional mental states such as beliefs and
desires, though they may have inward manifestations in the
form of the individual's private thoughts, are no more
inside the brains of their owners than is the magnetic
field of an iron bar inside the bar. Like all
dispositional properties, mental dispositions depend for
their existence on a state of the structure, usually the
microstructure of the property-bearer. In the case of
mental dispositions this is invariably a state of the
microstructure of the brain, presumably a pattern of
`weights' at the synapses in the brain. But these states
of the brain microstructure stand as cause to the
dispositional states as effect. It follows, in accordance
with Hume's principle, that they are `distinct existences'.
Contrary to the view expressed by Searle, you can't have it
both ways. If two things are causally connected, they
can't be the same thing. If they're the same thing, they
can't be causally connected. Think of the relation between
the cubic capacity of the cylinders of an internal
combustion engine and its horsepower.
Instantaneous mental events are more difficult. They
occur at the interface between an antecedent mental process
and a subsequent and consequent dispositional mental state.
The antecedent mental process, according to me, is a
process in the brain; whereas the subsequent and consequent
disposition depends on, but is not, a state of the brain.
Consequently the instantaneous event at the interface
between the two can be thought of either as completing a
process in the brain or as initiating a brain state which
in turn gives the organism whose brain it is a
dispositional property it did not have before, and which is
something over and above the state of the brain on which it
depends. On balance, since they only initiate dispositonal
mental states by producing the relevant changes in the
brain microstructure, it seems right to view such events as
brain events simpliciter.
Turning to the phenomenon of consciousness considered
as an ongoing process a part of which (the individual's
private conscious experience) is susceptible to description
by the introspecting human subject and which, according to
me is almost certainly identical with some as yet
unspecified process in the brain. All the evidence both
from neurology and from brain imaging makes it pretty clear
that in mammals the cerebral cortex is the seat of
consciousness in this sense. Although there are many
processes and events in the cortex which are not
represented in the subject's introspective reports, if we
take consciousness to consist, as the evidence suggests, in
the process whereby inputs which are identified as
problematic by the subconscious system in the midbrain are
categorized and an appropriate response selected, there
seems to be no activity in the cortex that does not
subserve this basic problem-solving function. Sub-
conscious centres in the mid- and hind-brain, not to
mention the spinal cord, have important coordinating
functions both in relation to the execution of complex
skilled and habitual behavior, as well as in relation to
the involuntary attraction of attention to problematic
inputs; but when the organism is running on `automatic
pilot' in this way, the brain imaging evidence shows that
cortex is almost completely quiescent. What becomes of the
the mind in all this? It's just not a useful concept.
Kind regards,
Ullin Place
1/17/98
I have some reactions to some questions you raise at the end of your
paper where you ask:
>Are you personally willing to give up the idea of sense data as a
>foundation for knowledge?
I gave up that idea fifty years ago when I heard John Austin give
his `Sense and sensibilia' Lectures in Magdalen College, Oxford, in
1947.
>What would you loose by doing this?
Nothing.
>If you did give up this idea, would something like the pragmatist
>concept of experience be an effective substitute?
If I understand it which I probably don't, the pragmatist concept
of experience is an attempt to capture the notion of experience in
the phrase `learning from experience'. This is no substitute in my
view for the notion of sensory or phenomenal experience as that
which we describe when we describe what it is like to be aware of
this or that, of undergoing this or that or of doing this or
that. The two notions are connected; but nevertheless distinct. We
need both.
>For those of you who are trained in Neuroscience, which concept of
>experience seems more biologically plausible?
I am not sure that I can claim to be trained in Neuroscience; but
response of some eminent neuroscientists to what I have been
writing recently on these topics encourages me to think that I can
speak with some authority on this matter. As soon as I read the
late Donald Broadbent's 1971 book DECISION AND STRESS, it seemed
to me obvious that his concept of a "state of evidence" on the
basis of which the brain categorizes sensory inputs corresponds
rather precisely to the notion of raw uninterpreted sensory
experience. This notion I take to be implicit both in James'
description of the consciousness of the child as a "big blooming
buzzing confusion" and in Wilhelm Wundt's distinction between
Immediate and Mediate Experience, where Mediate Experience is
experience interpreted as a sensory encounter with external reality
and Immediate Experience is the same experience interpreted as what
it really is, a process taking place within the observer's own
consciousness. In ordinary language it is implicit in the
distinction we draw between `physical' pleasure and pain which
does not depend on how the stimulus is interpreted and `mental'
pleasure and pain which DOES so depend.
Regards,
Ullin
2/17/98
Dear Teed,
I would like to comment on the sensation/perception issue.
The traditional view of this matter to which I subscribe
holds that sensation + concept = perception. This formula implies
that there can be such a thing as a `raw', i.e., uninterpreted,
sensory experience. As evidence that such a notion is needed, I
would cite the distinction we draw between `physical' pleasure or
pain, where the pleasure or pain reaction is a response simply to
the quality of the sensory experience, and `mental' pleasure or
pain, where it is a response, sometimes to the very same
experience, once it has been conceptualised or interpreted, e.g.,
as a symptom of some fatal illness.
This notion of `raw' unconceptualised experience is
anathema to the Kantians and the phenomenologists; and there are at
least three sets of considerations which lend support to their
view. One is the relatively trivial point that you can't say
anything about an experience until it has been conceptualised in
SOME way. Another is the point that the qualia merchants are in
danger of overlooking, namely, that an unconceptualised experience
is like a unfertilised egg, an entity that has failed to fulfill
its biological function. But it is the third consideration which,
to my mind, is the most interesting. It is a point which is
suggested by a lot of recent neurological and neuropsychological
work, particularly the work that has been done on the functions of
the extra-striate visual areas, V2-V5. Contrary to what is suggested
by the adjective `raw', it is now becoming clear that a great deal of
complex processing has to go on in assembling the experience, BEFORE
it becomes what Broadbent (1971) calls "a state of evidence"
capable of suggesting an interpretation/conceptualisation/
categorization. What seems to happen in visual areas V1-V5 is that
there are specific neurons in these areas which are "tuned" to
respond to features of the input which become more and more
abstract and are triggered by retinal stimulation over wider and
wider areas the further removed they are from V1. These features
are things like an edge, a gradient of texture (interpreted as a
surface at certain angle of slope relative to the horizontal -
Gibson 1950) or a stationary object with a background moving to the
right (interpreted as watching an object moving to the left -
Gibson op.cit.) which are seldom, if ever, conceptualised as such,
but which, when "bound" together with other such features result in
a recognisable "image" of an object of some identifiable kind.
When one way of "binding" a set of features together fails to yield
an identifiable object, another way of "binding" the features may
be tried and, failing that, the standard reaction is to look again,
this time more closely.
Morover, the phenomenon of simultanagnosia which results
from lesions of this so-called "ventral stream" and which consists
in an inability to perceive the relations between different
objects in a visual array, even though the objects themsleves are
recognised normally, suggests that the interpretation of a complex
visual array proceeds in two stages. In the first stage the
individual objects are identified. In the second the
experience/"evidence" is revisited in order to conceptualise the
relations between them.
The complexity of this process and that of the processes
of response-selection and response execution which ensue, not to
mention the linguistic processes of assigning a name to a concept or
a concept to a name and of organizing and deciphering complex
sentence structures, explains why it is that only PROBLEMATIC
INPUTS (i.e., those that are either unexpected or significant
relative to the organism's motivational concerns) are processed in
this way. The task of separating the problematic from the
unproblematic, alerting consciousness to the former, while either
ignoring the latter or routeing them automatically and unconsciously
along well-worn channels to output, falls to the automatic-pilot or
"zombie-within" as I call it.
Regards,
Ullin
7/16/98
Dear Teed,
16 July 1998
If, as seems reasonable, your criterion for the
presence and absence of consciousness is the presence or
absence of conscious/phenomenal experience, we now have
conclusive empirical evidence showing that the function
of conscious/phenomenal experience is to provide what
Broadbent (1971) calls the "evidence" on which the
categorization of problematic inputs (inputs which are
either unexpected or significant relative to the
organism's current or perennial motivational concerns) is
based. This evidence comes from the work on the effect
of lesions of the striate cortex in man (Weiskrantz 1986)
and in monkeys (Humphrey 1974; Cowey & Stoerig 1995). We
know from the "blindsight" evidence assembled by
Weiskrantz that the effect of lesions of the striate
cortex in man is to abolish visual conscious experience
in the affected part of the visual field. Some visual
discriminations are still possible to objects in the
affected part of the field, but are described by the
subject as "pure guesswork". The Cowey & Stoerig
experiment shows that the principal effect of a near
total ablation of the striate cortex in a monkey is to
deprive the animal of the ability to categorize its
visual inputs. The work of Broadbent (1958; 1971) on the
so-called "cocktail party effect" in the auditory
modality shows that the function of selective attention,
both involuntary and voluntary, in relation to the
initial processing of sensory input is to protect the
perceptual categorization mechanism from overload by
focusing on the problematic at the expense of the non-
problematic. Subsequent work by Pashler (1991; 1997) and
Posner (Posner & Petersen, 1990; Posner & Dehaene 1994)
shows that the selective attention which controls the
processing of sensory input (the posterior attentional
system - superior colliculus; pulvinar and posterior
parietal cortex) is to be distinguished from another such
system (the anterior attentional system-anterior
cingulate and basal ganglia) which controls access from
the output of the perceptual categorization system into
another limited capacity channel whose function is to
select a response appropriate to a situation of the type
that has been identified by the categorizer as being
currently present.
In the light of this evidence I have no hesitation
in concluding that the Rodney Brooks machine is conscious
and that the Minsky machine is not. Sadly, I have to say
that the argument on which this conclusion is reached
owes virtually everything to empirical neuropsychology
and almost nothing to philosophy. This, so it seems to
me, is the end of the line as far as the philosopher's
involvement in the mind-body problem is concerned. Just
as the problem of the origin of the universe has ceased
during our lifetime to be a problem in theology and
become an empirically decideable issue within astronomy;
so, as I foresaw in 1956, the mind-body problem is
ceasing to be a philosophical problem and becoming an
empirically decideable issue in neuroscience.
Regards,
Ullin
1/22/98
Dear Teed,
A few points in response to your `Beating of an
undead horse'. The first relates to the difference
between James' "big blooming buzzing confusion" and my
Wundt and "physical" v. "mental" pleasure and pain cases.
What is true is that James identifies what he takes to be
an actual case where experience (as a whole - yes)
remains uninterpreted, because the child hasn't yet
developed the required concepts. Wundt's two forms of
experience do not involve uninterpreted experience in
this sense. It's simply that according to him there are
two different ways in which the SAME experience can be
interpreted which implies that the experience and its
interpretation are two different things. There is no
reason to hold on to this view that any uninterpreted
experience exists, except perhaps momentarily before an
interpretation is arrived at or when switching from one
interpretation to another.
The pleasure/pain case is slightly different. Here
the suggestion is that in the case of "physical" pleasure
and pain the emotional response DOES NOT DEPEND ON the
way the experience is interpreted. Again there is
nothing that requires the actual existence of
uninterpreted experiences.
My second point relates to Broadbent's use of the
term "evidence". When I use this term in my own work, I
always put it in quotation marks. This is because,
according to me, it is not evidence in the ordinary sense
of that word. It is precisely because the use of the
term `data', together with the phenomenalist theoretical
framework in which it is embedded, treats sense-data as
evidence in the ordinary sense that leads me to say that
sense-data do not exist. The same incidentally goes for
qualia, if it is taken to be part of the definition of a
quale that it is a functionless epiphenomenon. But if
you say that sense-data are data only in metaphorical
sense or if you allow that qualia have a vital function
in the process that leads to sense perception, I am happy
to use both expressions and say that a sense datum is a
private sensory experience and that a quale is a property
of such an experience by which we recognise the stimulus
situation confronting us as one of this or that kind.
What is wrong with treating sensory experience as
evidence for the belief that one is confronted by a
situation of this or that kind in one's external
environment is that we ordinarily use the term `evidence'
(a) when talking about the relation between two
statements or sets of statements, the evidence on
the one hand and the hypothesis it is evidence for
on the other,
(b) where the evidence consists in one or more
observation statements and where the hypothesis for
which the observation statements provide evidence is
something that cannot itself be directly observed.
In the case of the relation between sensory
experience and the categorization of it as an encounter
with a situation of this or that kind, neither of these
conditions apply.
(a) In the categorization of sensory input there are no statements
involved. Sensory experience and the categorization for which it
provides the evidence are neural processes which
occur in the brains of animals just as much as in
the brains of humans. Even in the human brain
identifying the kind of object or situation with
which one is confronted is a distinct process both
from that of naming the object or situation and
putting what is observed into words in the form of a
statement.
(b) Contrary to the opinion of the phenomenalists, in
the ordinary sense that word we DO directly perceive
the objects and situations in our stimulus
environment for whose presence sensory experience
and its qualia provides "evidence".
Contrary to the view expressed by Ryle in THE
CONCEPT OF MIND, there are cases where we can quite
properly be said to observe our sensations and other
private experiences. After filling a particularly deep
cavity in one of my teeth recently, my dentist asked me
to check any pain I might subsequently have to see
whether it was caused equally by hot and cold stimuli
(good) or only by hot (bad, particulary if throbbing).
This, however, is a rather sophisticated form of
observation which we learn only AFTER we have already
learned to observe what is going on in the world around
us. When I say I rejected the doctrine of sense-data
more than fifty years ago, what I rejected was the idea
that in observing what is going on around us, we begin by
observing our sensory experience, formulate those
observations in the form of a sentence in a private sense
datum language and then use those private observation
sentences as evidence for the existence and nature of
what we NEVER observe, namely the objects and situations
in the world around us.
That, of course, means that I rejected - here
following Wittgenstein - the notion that the observation
sentences which provide the foundation of empirical
knowledge are sentences in a sense-datum language
describing the private sensations of a single individual.
What it did not mean is that I denied either the
possibility of describing private experience or the idea
that empirical knowledge has to be anchored to
observation statements. With regard to the former, I
have been insisting for more than forty years that our
ability to describe our private experience is parasitical
on a prior ability to describe what is going on in the
public world. With regard to the latter, I have long
assumed, but rather more recently begun to insist, that the
observation statements which anchor our language to the reality it
enables us to depict are statements describing a publicly observable
state of affairs (events disappear too quickly) on whose correct
description any competent speaker of the natural language or
technical code in current use will agree. It is because I take
this principle as axiomatic that I describe myself as a
behaviorist. See `A my radical behaviorist methodology
for the empirical investigation of private events'
BEHAVIOR AND PHILOSOPHY, 1993, 20, 25-35.
One final point in this connection. The relation
between a sensory experience and the categorization of
the current state of the stimulus environment for which
it provides the "evidence" is a straightforward causal
relation; whereas the relation between evidence in the
ordinary sense and the hypothesis for which it provides
evidence is a logical relation. Logical relations such
as this can, of course, act as causes in persuading an
individual to accept (or sometimes reject) the hypothesis
for which it is evidence. But that does not alter the
fact that logical relations, as such, are not causal
relations. The analogy between the two cases is that in
both, it is important for the individual to GET IT RIGHT.
The difference is that in the experience-categorization
case what the individual has to get right is what it is
he or she is currently observing; whereas in the
evidence-hypothesis case what the individual has to get
right is a verbal description of something that is NOT
currently available for direct inspection.
Another difference is that all the might of
natural selection is mobilised to ensure the conformity of
our perceptual categorization to the way things are;
whereas, except in a handful of cases where getting it
right is a matter of life or death, there are only a few
relatively weak social sanctions to ensure that our
hypotheses are and remain consistent with the available
evidence.
Sergio Chaigneau's mention of J.J.Gibson reminds me
of my own excitement when, as a very inexperienced
psychology teacher at the University of Adelaide, I read
Gibson's first book THE PERCEPTION OF THE VISUAL WORLD
when it appeared in (?) 1951. Here for the first time
was a psychologist doing experimental work within a
conceptual framework entirely consistent with what I had
learned from Austin's `Sense and Sensibilia' lectures -
so different from the ghastly conceptual confusion of the
Gestalt Psychologists, whose work had been endlessly
thrust down my throat during my psychology course at
Oxford in 1947-9 and which was the principle target of
my critique of the phenomenological fallacy in `Is
consciousness a brain process?'.
During the winter of 1955 after I had returned to
Oxford from my four years at Adelaide and while I was
waiting for `Is consciousness a brain process?' to appear
in print, I had the privilege of getting to know Gibson
personally. He had a visiting appointment at the
Institute of Experimental Psychology where I was registered
as a candidate for the D.Phil., a degree which I never
managed to obtain. I tried to persuade him, unsuccessfully
as it turned out, that his position would be more consistent
if he dropped the phenomenological veneer and stated it in a
straightforward behaviorist way. Interestingly, I was
supported in this by his wife, Eleanor Gibson, who not only
worked on perception in animals, but had been a student of
Clark Hull at Yale. I have a copy of my correspondence with
J.J.G. during this period on file on my computer and could
e-mail it to you, if you're interested.
You might also be interested, in connection with Ruth
Milliken's deployment of Ryle's `knowing how' and
`knowing that' distinction, in a section of my chapter on
`Ryle's behaviourism [sic]' in W.O'Donohue and
R.Kitchener (eds.) HANDBOOK OF BEHAVIORISM which is
forthcoming from Academic Press. In it I discuss the
distinction and suggest that it marks a failure on Ryle's
part to study the grammatical objects of psychological
verbs with the same thoroughness with which he explored
their aspectual characteristics. This left room for
Roderick Chisholm to introduce his linguistified version
of Brentano's intentionality, thereby generating a new
piece of conceptual confusion for philosophers to pick
over.
This, of course, needn't undermine Ruth's thesis
which I would express in my behavioristic way by saying
that getting one's propositions right depends on a great
deal of contingency-shaped learning of semantic
conventions which in turn depends on the, part
contingency-shaped, part innate, pre-linguistic
categorization ability found in animals.
But please don't feel under any obligation to ask to see
either of these documents. You've got enough on your
plate as it is.
Regards
Ullin